+
JMJ
Obedience
as per St. Thomas
St. Thomas' description of obedience in the Summa is broken down
into six articles examining whether:- One man is bound to obey another? Yes, inferiors a bound to
obey their superiors.
- Obedience is a special virtue? Yes, it is a special virtue.
- Obedience is the greatest of all virtues? No, Charity is the
greatest virtue.
- God ought to be obeyed in all things? Yes, all are bound to
obey the Divine Command.
- Subjects are bound to obey their superiors in all things?
No, if the Superior commands something against God or outside of
their sphere of authority obedience is not required in the latter
and sinful in the former.
- Against God: We are bound to obey the divine command as
known through the Divine, Written and Natural Law. To disobey the these is to commit sin.
- Sphere of Authority: This defines the limits of authority.
St. Thomas speaks of the limits of authority for rulers, parents,
as well as religious leaders. In each case there is typically a
form of Law that defines the limits of authority. In the case of
religious, St. Thomas refers to the 'regular mode of life' which is
set out in the Rule of the institute to which a person binds
themselves.
- Against God: We are bound to obey the divine command as
known through the Divine, Written and Natural Law. To disobey the these is to commit sin.
- Christians are bound to obey the secular powers? Yes,
following the conditions defined above.
P^3
Links to other posts in this latest series on obedience
Introduction: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article.htmlObedience as per St. Thomas: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_23.html
DisObedience as per St. Thomas Aquinas: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_24.html
Key Distinctions: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_25.html
Application to the 1988 Consecrations: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_26.html
Conclusions: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_27.html
Objections: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_28.html
St. Thomas on Legitimate authority and obedience: http://tradicat.blogspot.ca/2017/07/breaking-down-st-thomas-summa-article_13.html
Question | St. Thomas' Answer |
Whether one man is bound to obey another? | It is prescribed (Heb. 13:17): "Obey your prelates and be subject to them." Just as the actions of natural things proceed from natural powers, so do human actions proceed from the human will. In natural things it behooved the higher to move the lower to their actions by the excellence of the natural power bestowed on them by God: and so in human affairs also the higher must move the lower by their will in virtue of a divinely established authority. Now to move by reason and will is to command. Wherefore just as in virtue of the divinely established natural order the lower natural things need to be subject to the movement of the higher, so too in human affairs, in virtue of the order of natural and divine law, inferiors are bound to obey their superiors. |
Objection
1:It
seems that one man is not bound to obey another. For nothing
should be done contrary to the divine ordinance. Now God has so
ordered that man is ruled by his own counsel, according to Ecclus.
15:14, "God made man from the beginning, and left him in the
hand of his own counsel." Therefore one man is not bound to
obey another. Reply to Objection 1:God left man in the hand of his own counsel, not as though it were lawful to him to do whatever he will, but because, unlike irrational creatures, he is not compelled by natural necessity to do what he ought to do, but is left the free choice proceeding from his own counsel. And just as he has to proceed on his own counsel in doing other things, so too has he in the point of obeying his superiors. For Gregory says (Moral. xxxv), "When we humbly give way to another's voice, we overcome ourselves in our own hearts." |
|
Objection
2:Further,
if one man were bound to obey another, he would have to look upon
the will of the person commanding him, as being his rule of
conduct. Now God's will alone, which is always right, is a rule of
human conduct. Therefore man is bound to obey none but God. Reply to Objection 2:The will of God is the first rule whereby all rational wills are regulated: and to this rule one will approaches more than another, according to a divinely appointed order. Hence the will of the one man who issues a command may be as a second rule to the will of this other man who obeys him. |
|
Objection
3:Further,
the more gratuitous the service the more is it acceptable. Now
what a man does out of duty is not gratuitous. Therefore if a man
were bound in duty to obey others in doing good deeds, for this
very reason his good deeds would be rendered less acceptable
through being done out of obedience. Therefore one man is not
bound to obey another. Reply to Objection 3:A thing may be deemed gratuitous in two ways. In one way on the part of the deed itself, because, to wit, one is not bound to do it; in another way, on the part of the doer, because he does it of his own free will. Now a deed is rendered virtuous, praiseworthy and meritorious, chiefly according as it proceeds from the will. Wherefore although obedience be a duty, if one obey with a prompt will, one's merit is not for that reason diminished, especially before God, Who sees not only the outward deed, but also the inward will. |
|
Whether obedience is a special virtue? | Obedience
is reckoned by some to be a part of justice, as stated above
(Question
[80]). A special virtue is assigned to all good deeds that have a special reason of praise: for it belongs properly to virtue to render a deed good. Now obedience to a superior is due in accordance with the divinely established order of things, as shown above (Article [1]), and therefore it is a good, since good consists in mode, species and order, as Augustine states (De Natura Boni iii) [*Cf. FP,Question [5],Article [5]]. Again, this act has a special aspect of praiseworthiness by reason of its object. For while subjects have many obligations towards their superiors, this one, that they are bound to obey their commands, stands out as special among the rest. Wherefore obedience is a special virtue, and its specific object is a command tacit or express, because the superior's will, however it become known, is a tacit precept, and a man's obedience seems to be all the more prompt, forasmuch as by obeying he forestalls the express command as soon as he understands his superior's will. |
Objection
1:It
seems that obedience is not a special virtue. For disobedience is
contrary to obedience. But disobedience is a general sin, because
Ambrose says (De Parad. viii) that "sin is to disobey the
divine law." Therefore obedience is not a special virtue. Reply to Objection 1:Nothing prevents the one same material object from admitting two special aspects to which two special virtues correspond: thus a soldier, by defending his king's fortress, fulfils both an act of fortitude, by facing the danger of death for a good end, and an act of justice, by rendering due service to his lord. Accordingly the aspect of precept, which obedience considers, occurs in acts of all virtues, but not in all acts of virtue, since not all acts of virtue are a matter of precept, as stated above (FS,Question [96],Article [3]). Moreover, certain things are sometimes a matter of precept, and pertain to no other virtue, such things for instance as are not evil except because they are forbidden. Wherefore, if obedience be taken in its proper sense, as considering formally and intentionally the aspect of precept, it will be a special virtue, and disobedience a special sin: because in this way it is requisite for obedience that one perform an act of justice or of some other virtue with the intention of fulfilling a precept; and for disobedience that one treat the precept with actual contempt. On the other hand, if obedience be taken in a wide sense for the performance of any action that may be a matter of precept, and disobedience for the omission of that action through any intention whatever, then obedience will be a general virtue, and disobedience a general sin. |
|
Objection
2:Further,
every special virtue is either theological or moral. But obedience
is not a theological virtue, since it is not comprised under
faith, hope or charity. Nor is it a moral virtue, since it does
not hold the mean between excess and deficiency, for the more
obedient one is the more is one praised. Therefore obedience is
not a special virtue. Reply to Objection 2:Obedience is not a theological virtue, for its direct object is not God, but the precept of any superior, whether expressed or inferred, namely, a simple word of the superior, indicating his will, and which the obedient subject obeys promptly, according to Titus 3:1, "Admonish them to be subject to princes, and to obey at a word," etc. It is, however, a moral virtue, since it is a part of justice, and it observes the mean between excess and deficiency. Excess thereof is measured in respect, not of quantity, but of other circumstances, in so far as a man obeys either whom he ought not, or in matters wherein he ought not to obey, as we have stated above regarding religion (Question [92],Article [2]). We may also reply that as in justice, excess is in the person who retains another's property, and deficiency in the person who does not receive his due, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. v, 4), so too obedience observes the mean between excess on the part of him who fails to pay due obedience to his superior, since he exceeds in fulfilling his own will, and deficiency on the part of the superior, who does not receive obedience. Wherefore in this way obedience will be a mean between two forms of wickedness, as was stated above concerning justice (Question [58],Article [10]). |
|
Objection
3:Further,
Gregory says (Moral. xxxv) that "obedience is the more
meritorious and praiseworthy, the less it holds its own." But
every special virtue is the more to be praised the more it holds
its own, since virtue requires a man to exercise his will and
choice, as stated in Ethic. ii, 4. Therefore obedience is not a
special virtue.
Reply
to Objection 3:Obedience,
like every virtue requires the will to be prompt towards its
proper object, but not towards that which is repugnant to it. Now
the proper
object of obedience is a precept,
and this proceeds from another's will. Wherefore obedience make a
man's will prompt in fulfilling the will of another, the maker,
namely, of the precept. If that which is prescribed to him is
willed by him for its own sake apart from its being prescribed, as
happens in agreeable matters, he tends towards it at once by his
own will and seems to comply, not on account of the precept, but
on account of his own will. But if that which is prescribed is
nowise willed for its own sake, but, considered in itself,
repugnant to his own will, as happens in disagreeable matters,
then it is quite evident that it is not fulfilled except on
account of the precept. Hence Gregory says (Moral. xxxv) that
"obedience perishes or diminishes when it holds its own in
agreeable matters," because, to wit, one's own will seems to
tend principally, not to the accomplishment of the precept, but to
the fulfilment of one's own desire; but that "it increases in
disagreeable or difficult matters," because there one's own
will tends to nothing beside the precept. Yet
this must be understood as regards outward appearances: for, on
the other hand, according to the judgment of God, Who searches the
heart, it may happen that even in agreeable matters obedience,
while holding its own, is nonetheless praiseworthy, provided the
will of him that obeys tend no less devotedly [*Cf. Question [82],
Article [2]] to the fulfilment of the precept. |
|
Objection
4:Further,
virtues differ in species according to their objects. Now the
object of obedience would seem to be the command of a superior, of
which, apparently, there are as many kinds as there are degrees of
superiority. Therefore obedience is a general virtue, comprising
many special virtues. Reply to Objection 4:Reverence regards directly the person that excels: wherefore it admits a various species according to the various aspects of excellence. Obedience, on the other hand, regards the precept of the person that excels, and therefore admits of only one aspect. And since obedience is due to a person's precept on account of reverence to him, it follows that obedience to a man is of one species, though the causes from which it proceeds differ specifically. |
|
Whether obedience is the greatest of the virtues? | Obedience
deserves praise because it proceeds from charity: for Gregory says
(Moral. xxxv) that "obedience
should be practiced, not out of servile fear, but from a sense of
charity, not through fear of punishment, but through love of
justice."
Therefore charity is a greater virtue than obedience.
Just
as sin consists in man contemning God and adhering to mutable
things, so the merit of a virtuous act consists in man contemning
created goods and adhering to God as his end. Now the end is
greater than that which is directed to the end. Therefore if a man
contemns created goods in order that he may adhere to God, his
virtue derives greater praise from his adhering to God than from
his contemning earthly things. And so those, namely the
theological, virtues whereby he adheres to God in Himself, are
greater than the moral virtues, whereby he holds in contempt some
earthly thing in order to adhere to God.
Among
the moral virtues, the greater the thing which a man contemns that
he may adhere to God, the greater the virtue. Now there are three
kinds of human goods that man may contemn for God's sake. The
lowest of these are external goods, the goods of the body take the
middle place, and the highest are the goods of the soul; and among
these the chief, in a way, is the will, in so far as, by his will,
man makes use of all other goods. Therefore,
properly speaking, the virtue of obedience, whereby we contemn our
own will for God's sake, is more praiseworthy than the other moral
virtues, which contemn other goods for the sake of God.Hence Gregory says (Moral. xxxv) that "obedience is rightly preferred to sacrifices, because by sacrifices another's body is slain whereas by obedience we slay our own will." Wherefore even any other acts of virtue are meritorious before God through being performed out of obedience to God's will. For were one to suffer even martyrdom, or to give all one's goods to the poor, unless one directed these things to the fulfilment of the divine will, which pertains directly to obedience, they could not be meritorious: as neither would they be if they were done without charity, which cannot exist apart from obedience. For it is written (1 Jn. 2:4,5): "He who saith that he knoweth God, and keepeth not His commandments, is a liar . . . but he that keepeth His word, in him in very deed the charity of God is perfected": and this because friends have the same likes and dislikes. |
Objection
1:It
seems that obedience is the greatest of the virtues. For it is
written (1
Kgs. 15:22):
"Obedience is better than sacrifices." Now the offering
of sacrifices belongs to religion, which is the greatest of all
moral virtues, as shown above (Question
[81],Article
[6]).
Therefore obedience is the greatest of all virtues.
Reply
to Objection 1: Obedience
proceeds from reverence, which pays worship and honor to a
superior, and in this respect it is contained under different
virtues, although considered in itself, as regarding the aspect of
precept, it is one special virtue. Accordingly, in so far as it
proceeds from reverence for a superior, it is contained, in a way,
under observance; while in so far as it proceeds from reverence
for one's parents, it is contained under piety; and in so far as
it proceeds from reverence for God, it comes under religion, and
pertains to devotion, which is the principal act of religion.
Wherefore from this point of view it is more praiseworthy to obey
God than to offer sacrifice, as well as because, "in a
sacrifice we slay another's body, whereas by obedience we slay our
own will," as Gregory says (Moral. xxxv). As to the special
case in which Samuel spoke, it would have been better for Saul to
obey God than to offer in sacrifice the fat animals of the
Amalekites against the commandment of God. |
|
Objection
2:Further,
Gregory says (Moral. xxxv) that "obedience is the only virtue
that ingrafts virtues in the soul and protects them when
ingrafted." Now the cause is greater than the effect.
Therefore obedience is greater than all the virtues. Reply to Objection 2:All acts of virtue, in so far as they come under a precept, belong to obedience. Wherefore according as acts of virtue act causally or dispositively towards their generation and preservation, obedience is said to ingraft and protect all virtues. And yet it does not follow that obedience takes precedence of all virtues absolutely, for two reasons. First, because though an act of virtue come under a precept, one may nevertheless perform that act of virtue without considering the aspect of precept. Consequently, if there be any virtue, whose object is naturally prior to the precept, that virtue is said to be naturally prior to obedience. Such a virtue is faith, whereby we come to know the sublime nature of divine authority, by reason of which the power to command is competent to God. Secondly, because infusion of grace and virtues may precede, even in point of time, all virtuous acts: and in this way obedience is not prior to all virtues, neither in point of time nor by nature. |
|
Objection
3:Further,
Gregory says (Moral. xxxv) that "evil should never be done
out of obedience: yet sometimes for the sake of obedience we
should lay aside the good we are doing." Now one does not lay
aside a thing except for something better. Therefore obedience,
for whose sake the good of other virtues is set aside, is better
than other virtues. Reply to Objection 3:There are two kinds of good. There is that to which we are bound of necessity, for instance to love God, and so forth: and by no means may such a good be set aside on account of obedience. But there is another good to which man is not bound of necessity, and this good we ought sometimes to set aside for the sake of obedience to which we are bound of necessity, since we ought not to do good by falling into sin. Yet as Gregory remarks (Moral. xxxv), "he who forbids his subjects any single good, must needs allow them many others, lest the souls of those who obey perish utterly from starvation, through being deprived of every good." Thus the loss of one good may be compensated by obedience and other goods. |
|
Whether God ought to be obeyed in all things? | It
is written (Ex.
24:7):
"All things that the Lord hath spoken we will do, and we will
be obedient." As stated above (Article [1]), he who obeys is moved by the command of the person he obeys, just as natural things are moved by their motive causes. Now just a God is the first mover of all things that are moved naturally, so too is He the first mover of all wills, as shown above (FS,Question [9],Article [6]). Therefore just as all natural things are subject to the divine motion by a natural necessity so too all wills, by a kind of necessity of justice, are bound to obey the divine command. |
Objection
1:It
seems that God need not be obeyed in all things. For it is written
(Mt.
9:30,31)
that our Lord after healing the two blind men commanded them,
saying: "See that no man know this. But they going out spread
His fame abroad in all that country." Yet they are not blamed
for so doing. Therefore it seems that we are not bound to obey God
in all things. Reply to Objection 1:Our Lord in telling the blind men to conceal the miracle had no intention of binding them with the force of a divine precept, but, as Gregory says (Moral. xix), "gave an example to His servants who follow Him that they might wish to hide their virtue and yet that it should be proclaimed against their will, in order that others might profit by their example." |
|
Objection
2:Further,
no one is bound to do anything contrary to virtue. Now we find
that God commanded certain things contrary to virtue: thus He
commanded Abraham to slay his innocent son (Gn.
22);
and the Jews to steal the property of the Egyptians (Ex.
11),
which things are contrary to justice; and Hosea to take to himself
a woman who was an adulteress (Hosea 3), and this is contrary to
chastity. Therefore God is not to be obeyed in all things. Reply to Objection 2:Even as God does nothing contrary to nature (since "the nature of a thing is what God does therein," according to a gloss on Rm. 11), and yet does certain things contrary to the wonted course of nature; so to God can command nothing contrary to virtue since virtue and rectitude of human will consist chiefly in conformity with God's will and obedience to His command, although it be contrary to the wonted mode of virtue. Accordingly, then, the command given to Abraham to slay his innocent son was not contrary to justice, since God is the author of life and death. Nor again was it contrary to justice that He commanded the Jews to take things belonging to the Egyptians, because all things are His, and He gives them to whom He will. Nor was it contrary to chastity that Hosea was commanded to take an adulteress, because God Himself is the ordainer of human generation, and the right manner of intercourse with woman is that which He appoints. Hence it is evident that the persons aforesaid did not sin, either by obeying God or by willing to obey Him. |
|
Objection
3:Further,
whoever obeys God conforms his will to the divine will even as to
the thing willed. But we are not bound in all things to conform
our will to the divine will as to the thing willed, as stated
above (FS,Question
[19],Article
[10]). Therefore man is not bound to obey God in all things. Reply to Objection 3:Though man is not always bound to will what God wills, yet he is always bound to will what God wills him to will. This comes to man's knowledge chiefly through God's command, wherefore man is bound to obey God's commands in all things. |
|
Whether subjects are bound to obey their superiors in all things? | It
is written (Acts
5:29):
"We ought to obey God rather than men." Now sometimes
the things
commanded by a superior are against God. Therefore superiors are
not to be obeyed in all things.
As
stated above (Articles
[1],4),
he who obeys is moved at the bidding of the person who commands
him, by a certain necessity of justice, even as a natural thing is
moved through the power of its mover by a natural necessity. That
a natural thing be not moved by its mover, may happen in two ways.
First, on account of a hindrance arising from the stronger power
of some other mover; thus wood is not burnt by fire if a stronger
force of water intervene. Secondly, through lack of order in the
movable with regard to its mover, since, though it is subject to
the latter's action in one respect, yet it is not subject thereto
in every respect. Thus, a humor is sometimes subject to the action
of heat, as regards being heated, but not as regards being dried
up or consumed. In like manner there are two reasons, for which a
subject may not be bound to obey his superior in all things. First
on account of the command of a higher power. For as a gloss says
on Rm. 13:2, "They that resist [Vulg.: 'He that resisteth']
the power, resist the ordinance of God" (cf. St. Augustine,
De Verb. Dom. viii). "If a commissioner issue an order, are
you to comply, if it is contrary to the bidding of the proconsul?
Again if the proconsul command one thing, and the emperor another,
will you hesitate, to disregard the former and serve the latter?
Therefore if the emperor commands one thing and God another, you
must disregard the former and obey God." Secondly,
a subject is not bound to obey his superior if the latter command
him to do something wherein he is not subject to him.
For Seneca says (De Beneficiis iii): "It is wrong to suppose
that slavery falls upon the whole man: for the better part of him
is excepted." His body is subjected and assigned to his
master but his soul is his own. Consequently in matters touching
the internal movement of the will man is not bound to obey his
fellow-man, but God alone.
Nevertheless
man is bound to obey his fellow-man in things that have to be done
externally by means of the body: and yet, since by nature all men
are equal, he is not bound to obey another man in matters touching
the nature of the body, for instance in those relating to the
support of his body or the begetting of his children. Wherefore
servants are not bound to obey their masters, nor children their
parents, in the question of contracting marriage or of remaining
in the state of virginity or the like. But
in matters concerning the disposal of actions and human affairs, a
subject is bound to obey his superior within the sphere of his
authority;
for instance a soldier must obey his general in matters relating
to war, a servant his master in matters touching the execution of
the duties of his service, a son his father in matters relating to
the conduct of his life and the care of the household; and so
forth. |
Objection
1:It
seems that subjects are bound to obey their superiors in all
things. For the Apostle says (Col. 3:20): "Children, obey
your parents in all things," and farther on (Col. 3:22):
"Servants, obey in all things your masters according to the
flesh." Therefore in like manner other subjects are bound to
obey their superiors in all things. Reply to Objection 1:When the Apostle says "in all things," he refers to matters within the sphere of a father's or master's authority. |
|
Objection
2:Further,
superiors stand between God and their subjects, according to Dt.
5:5, "I was the mediator and stood between the Lord and you
at that time, to show you His words." Now there is no going
from extreme to extreme, except through that which stands between.
Therefore the commands of a superior must be esteemed the commands
of God, wherefore the Apostle says (Gal.
4:14): "You . . . received me as an angel of God, even as
Christ Jesus" and (1
Thess. 2:13): "When you had received of us the word of
the hearing of God, you received it, not as the word of men, but,
as it is indeed, the word of God." Therefore as man is bound
to obey God in all things, so is he bound to obey his superiors. Reply to Objection 2:Man is subject to God simply as regards all things, both internal and external, wherefore he is bound to obey Him in all things. On the other hand, inferiors are not subject to their superiors in all things, but only in certain things and in a particular way, in respect of which the superior stands between God and his subjects, whereas in respect of other matters the subject is immediately under God, by Whom he is taught either by the natural or by the written law. |
|
Objection
3:Further,
just as religious in making their profession take vows of chastity
and poverty, so do they also vow obedience. Now a religious is
bound to observe chastity and poverty in all things. Therefore he
is also bound to obey in all things. Reply to Objection 3:Religious profess obedience as to the regular mode of life, in respect of which they are subject to their superiors: wherefore they are bound to obey in those matters only which may belong to the regular mode of life, and this obedience suffices for salvation. If they be willing to obey even in other matters, this will belong to the superabundance of perfection; provided, however, such things be not contrary to God or to the rule they profess, for obedience in this case would be unlawful. Accordingly we may distinguish a threefold obedience; one, sufficient for salvation, and consisting in obeying when one is bound to obey: secondly, perfect obedience, which obeys in all things lawful: thirdly, indiscreet obedience, which obeys even in matters unlawful. |
|
Whether Christians are bound to obey the secular powers? | It
is written (Titus
3:1):
"Admonish them to be subject to princes and powers," and
(1
Pt. 2:13,14):
"Be ye subject . . . to every human creature for God's sake:
whether it be to the king as excelling, or to governors as sent by
him." Faith in Christ is the origin and cause of justice, according to Rm. 3:22, "The justice of God by faith of Jesus Christ:" wherefore faith in Christ does not void the order of justice, but strengthens it." Now the order of justice requires that subjects obey their superiors, else the stability of human affairs would cease. Hence faith in Christ does not excuse the faithful from the obligation of obeying secular princes. |
Objection
1:It
seems that Christians are not bound to obey the secular power. For
a gloss on Mt. 17:25, "Then the children are free,"
says: "If in every kingdom the children of the king who holds
sway over that kingdom are free, then the children of that King,
under Whose sway are all kingdoms, should be free in every
kingdom." Now Christians, by their faith in Christ, are made
children of God, according to Jn. 1:12: "He gave them power
to be made the sons of God, to them that believe in His name."
Therefore they are not bound to obey the secular power. Reply to Objection 1:As stated above (Article [5]), subjection whereby one man is bound to another regards the body; not the soul, which retains its liberty. Now, in this state of life we are freed by the grace of Christ from defects of the soul, but not from defects of the body, as the Apostle declares by saying of himself (Rm. 7:23) that in his mind he served the law of God, but in his flesh the law of sin. Wherefore those that are made children of God by grace are free from the spiritual bondage of sin, but not from the bodily bondage, whereby they are held bound to earthly masters, as a gloss observes on 1 Tim. 6:1, "Whosoever are servants under the yoke," etc. |
|
Objection
2:Further,
it is written (Rm.
7:4):
"You . . . are become dead to the law by the body of Christ,"
and the law mentioned here is the divine law of the Old Testament.
Now human law whereby men are subject to the secular power is of
less account than the divine law of the Old Testament. Much more,
therefore, since they have become members of Christ's body, are
men freed from the law of subjection, whereby they were under the
power of secular princes. Reply to Objection 2:The Old Law was a figure of the New Testament, and therefore it had to cease on the advent of truth. And the comparison with human law does not stand because thereby one man is subject to another. Yet man is bound by divine law to obey his fellow-man. |
|
Objection
3:Further,
men are not bound to obey robbers, who oppress them with violence.
Now, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei iv): "Without justice, what
else is a kingdom but a huge robbery?" Since therefore the
authority of secular princes is frequently exercised with
injustice, or owes its origin to some unjust usurpation, it seems
that Christians ought not to obey secular princes. Reply to Objection 3:Man is bound to obey secular princes in so far as this is required by order of justice. Wherefore if the prince's authority is not just but usurped, or if he commands what is unjust, his subjects are not bound to obey him, except perhaps accidentally, in order to avoid scandal or danger. |
Comments
Post a Comment